Skip to main content
Log in

On the axiomatic characterization of the coalitional multinomial probabilistic values

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
TOP Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The coalitional multinomial probabilistic values extend the notion of multinomial probabilistic value to games with a coalition structure, in such a way that they generalize the symmetric coalitional binomial semivalues and link and combine the Shapley value and the multinomial probabilistic values. By considering the property of balanced contributions within unions, a new axiomatic characterization is stated for each one of these coalitional values, provided that it is defined by a positive tendency profile, by means of a set of logically independent properties that univocally determine the value. Two applications are also shown: (a) to the Madrid Assembly in Legislature 2015–2019 and (b) to the Parliament of Andalucía in Legislature 2018–2022.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Condition (ii) ensures consistency with symmetric coalitional binomial semivalues (cf. Carreras and Puente 2006; Alonso et al. 2007; Carreras and Puente 2012).

  2. Although the results obtained in practice will depend in general on this mechanism.

  3. The reduced game to which the Shapley value is applied is as follows. First, if \(S\subseteq B_k\), let \({{\overline{v}}}^B_S\) be the pseudoquotient game in M defined by

    $$\begin{aligned} {{\overline{v}}}^B_S(R)=v\Big [(\bigcup _{r\in R}B_r)\backslash (B_k\backslash S)\Big ]\quad \text { for each}\quad R\subseteq M. \end{aligned}$$

    This game is the modification of the standard quotient game \(v^B\) when S replaces union \(B_k\), as if the players of \(B_k\backslash S\) were temporarily inactive. The reduced game of v in \(B_k\), denoted by \(w_k\), is then given by

    $$\begin{aligned} w_k(S)=\lambda ^{\overline{{\varvec{p}}}}_k[{{\overline{v}}}^B_S]\quad \text { for each}\quad S\subseteq B_k. \end{aligned}$$
  4. In principle, this property makes sense only for coalitional values defined for all N; in such a case, one generally abuses the notation and uses a unique symbol g on both \({\mathcal {G}}_N^{{\text {CS}}}\) and \({\mathcal {G}}_M^{\text {CS}}\). However, the property also makes sense for a coalitional value g on a given \({\mathcal {G}}_N^{{\text {cs}}}\) provided, at least, that it induces a coalitional value \({{\overline{g}}}\) on \({\mathcal {G}}_M^{{\text {cs}}}\) for each \(B\in B(N)\). And this is precisely the case of the coalitional multinomial probabilistic values.

References

  • Alonso JM, Fiestras MG (2002) Modification of the Banzhaf value for games with a coalition structure. Ann Oper Res 109:213–227

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alonso JM, Carreras F, Puente MA (2007) Axiomatic characterizations of the symmetric coalitional binomial semivalues. Discret Appl Math 155:2282–2293

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amer R, Carreras F, Giménez JM (2002) The modified Banzhaf value for games with coalition structure: an axiomatic characterization. Math Soc Sci 43:45–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banzhaf JF (1965) Weigthed voting doesnt work: a mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Rev 19:317–343

    Google Scholar 

  • Carreras F, Puente MA (2006) A parametric family of mixed coalitional values. In: Seeger A (ed) Recent advances in optimization, lecture notes in economics and mathematical systems. Springer, New York, pp 323–339

    Google Scholar 

  • Carreras F, Puente MA (2012) Symmetric coalitional binomial semivalues. Group Decis Negot 21:637–662

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carreras F, Puente MA (2015a) Multinomial probabilistic values. Group Decis Negot 24:981–991

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carreras F, Puente MA (2015b) Coalitional multinomial probabilistic values. Eur J Oper Res 245:236–246

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carreras F, Puente MA (2018) A note on multinomial probabilistic values. TOP 26:164–186

    Google Scholar 

  • Domènech M, Giménez JM, Puente MA (2016) Some properties for probabilistic and multinomial (probabilistic) values on cooperative games. Optimization 65:1377–1395

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dragan I (1996) New mathematical properties of the Banzhaf value. Eur J Oper Res 95:451–463

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubey P, Shapley LS (1979) Mathematical properties of the Banzhaf power index. Math Oper Res 4:99–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freixas J, Puente MA (2002) Reliability importance measures of the components in a system based on semivalues and probabilistic values. Ann Oper Res 109:331–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giménez JM, Llongueras MD, Puente MA (2014) Partnership formation and multinomial values. Discret Appl Math 170:7–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owen G (1975) Multilinear extensions and the Banzhaf value. Naval Res Logist Q 22:741–750

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owen G (1977) Values of games with a priori unions. In: Henn R, Moeschlin O (eds) Mathematical economics and game theory. Springer, New York, pp 76–88

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Owen G (1982) Modification of the Banzhaf-Coleman index for games with a priori unions. In: Holler MJ (ed) Power, voting and voting power. Physica, Heidelberg, pp 232–238

    Google Scholar 

  • Puente MA (2000) Contributions to the representability of simple games and to the calculus of solutions for this class of game (in Spanish). Ph.D. Thesis. Universitat Politècnica de Catalunya, Spain

  • Shapley LS (1953) A value for n-person games. In: Kuhn HW, Tucker AW (eds) Contributions to the theory of games II. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 307–317

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber RJ (1988) Probabilistic values for games. In: Roth AE (ed) The Shapley value: essays in honor of Lloyd S. Shapley. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 101–119

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors wish to thank the managing editor for encouraging them to improve the paper, and two anonymous reviewers for their interesting comments and helpful suggestions, most of which have been incorporated into the text.

Funding

This research project was partially supported by funds from the Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation under Grant PID2019-104987GB-I00.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to María Albina Puente.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix: logical independence

Appendix: logical independence

Proposition A.1

The axiomatic system used in Theorem 3.2 is logically independent.

Proof

We will assume that a player set N (with \(n=|N|\ge 2\)) and a positive tendency profile \(\varvec{p}\) in N are given. We will abbreviate the properties as follows: LI = linearity, DP = dummy player property, BC = balanced contributions within unions, TP = coalitional \(\varvec{p}\)-multinomial total power property, and WU = property of \(\varvec{p}\)-weighted payoffs for quotients of unanimity games.

  1. 1.

    LI is logically independent of DP, BC, TP and WU. We define a coalitional value g for all \([v;B]\in {\mathcal {G}}_N^{{\text {cs}}}\) as follows.

    1. (a)

      Unanimity games. If \(v=u^T\) with \(\emptyset \ne T\subseteq N\) then

      $$\begin{aligned} g_i[v;B]=\Lambda _i^{\varvec{p}}[v;B]\quad \text { for each}i\in N. \end{aligned}$$
    2. (b)

      Otherwise, that is, if v is not a unanimity game,

      $$\begin{aligned} g_i[v;B]= {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \Lambda _i^{\varvec{p}}[v;B]=v(\{i\})\quad \text { if }i \text { is a dummy in} v,\\ \dfrac{1}{b'_k}\displaystyle \sum _{j\in B'_k}\Lambda _j^{\varvec{p}}[v;B] \quad \text { if} i\in B_k\in B \text { is not a dummy in }v, \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

      where \(B'_k\) denotes the set of players of \(B_k\) that are not dummies in v, and \(b'_k=|B'_k|\). DP, BC, TP and WU are clearly satisfied by g. However, this value fails to satisfy LI for e.g. game \(v=u^{\{1\}}+2u^{\{1,2\}}\) and the trivial coalition structure \(B=B^N\).

  2. 2.

    DP is logically independent of LI, BC, TP and WU. We define a coalitional value g for all \([v;B]\in {\mathcal {G}}_N^{{\text {cs}}}\) as follows. For each \(i\in N\),

    $$\begin{aligned} g_i[v;B]=\dfrac{v(N)}{n}\quad \text { if} \; B=B^N, \end{aligned}$$

    and otherwise

    $$\begin{aligned} g_i[v;B]=\Lambda _i^{\varvec{p}}[v;B]. \end{aligned}$$

    LI, BC, TP and WU are clearly satisfied by g. However, this value fails to satisfy DP for the unanimity game \(v=u^{\{1\}}\) and the trivial coalition structure \(B=B^N\).

  3. 3.

    BC is logically independent of LI, DP, TP and WU. We define a coalitional value g for all \([v;B]\in {\mathcal {G}}_N^{{\text {cs}}}\) as follows.

    1. (a)

      If \(n=2\) and \(B=B^N\), then

      $$\begin{aligned} {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} g_1[v;B]=v(\{1\}),\\ g_2[v;B]=v(N)-v(\{1\}).\\ \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
    2. (b)

      Otherwise, that is, if some of the above conditions does not hold,

      $$\begin{aligned} g_i[v;B]=\Lambda _i^{\varvec{p}}[v;B]\quad \text { for each }i\in N. \end{aligned}$$

      LI, DP, TP and WU are clearly satisfied by g. However, this value fails to satisfy BC for the unanimity game \(v=u^{\{1,2\}}\) and the trivial coalition structure \(B=B^N\).

  4. 4.

    TP is logically independent of LI, DP, BC and WU. We define a coalitional value g for all \([v;B]\in {\mathcal {G}}_N^{{\text {cs}}}\) as follows.

    1. (a)

      If \(n=2\) and \(B=B^n\), then

      $$\begin{aligned} {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} g_1[v;B]=v(\{1\}),\\ g_2[v;B]=v(\{2\}).\\ \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
    2. (b)

      Otherwise, that is, if some of the above conditions does not hold,

      $$\begin{aligned} g_i[v;B]=\Lambda _i^{\varvec{p}}[v;B]\quad \text { for each }i\in N. \end{aligned}$$

      LI, DP, BC and WU are clearly satisfied by g. However, this value fails to satisfy TP for the unanimity game \(v=u^{\{1,2\}}\) and the trivial coalition structure \(B=B^n\).

  5. 5.

    WU is logically independent of LI, DP, BC and TP. Let \(\alpha ,\beta \) be real numbers such that \(\alpha +\beta =p_1+p_2\) and \(\alpha p_1\ne \beta p_2\). We define a coalitional value g for all \([v;B]\in {\mathcal {G}}_N^{{\text {cs}}}\) as follows.

    1. (a)

      If \(n=2\) and \(B=B^n\), then

      $$\begin{aligned} {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} g_1[v;B]=v(\{1\})+\alpha [v(N)-v(\{1\})-v(\{2\})],\\ g_2[v;B]=v(\{2\})+\beta [v(N)-v(\{1\})-v(\{2\})].\\ \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
    2. (b)

      Otherwise, that is, if some of the above conditions does not hold,

      $$\begin{aligned} g_i[v;B]=\Lambda _i^{\varvec{p}}[v;B]\quad \text { for each }i\in N. \end{aligned}$$

      LI, DP, BC and TP are clearly satisfied by g. However, this value fails to satisfy WU for the unanimity game \(v=u^{\{1,2\}}\) and the trivial coalition structure \(B=B^n\).\(\square \)

Proposition A.2

The axiomatic system used in Theorem 3.4is logically independent.

Proof

We continue to assume that a player set N (with \(n=|N|\ge 2\)) and a positive tendency profile \(\varvec{p}\) in N are given. We will continue to abbreviate the properties as follows: LI = linearity, DP = dummy player property, BC = balanced contributions within unions, TP = coalitional \(\varvec{p}\)-multinomial total power property, and WU = property of \(\varvec{p}\)-weighted payoffs for quotients of unanimity games. We will also abbreviate TR = transfer property.

Let us consider now the restriction to simple games of each coalitional value g defined for Proposition A.1 in parts 2, 3, 4 and 5. In each case, this restriction is a coalitional power index that satisfies the desired properties with the sole exception of linearity, which does not make sense for simple games. But the transfer property is also satisfied by all these coalitional values. The argument is as follows.

The composition laws \(\vee \) and \(\wedge \) make sense and satisfy

$$\begin{aligned} u\vee v + u\wedge v = u + v, \end{aligned}$$

for all cooperative games. If u and v are simple games and, for a while, we think of them as cooperative games then, using linearity, we obtain for each g used in Proposition A.1

$$\begin{aligned} g[u\vee v;B] + g[u\wedge v;B] = g[u;B] + g[v;B]\quad \text { for all }B, \end{aligned}$$

which is precisely TR.

Moreover, all counterexamples provided in cases 2, 3, 4 and 5 for Proposition A.1 are simple games, so they can be used also for this Proposition A.2. Thus, it only remains to check the following.

1 bis. TR is logically independent of DP, BC, TP and WU.

We define a coalitional power index g for all \([v;B]\in \mathcal {SG}_N^{{\text {cs}}}\) as follows.

  1. (a)

    If \(n=2\), \(v=u^{\{1\}}\vee u^{\{2\}}\) and \(B=B^n\), then

    $$\begin{aligned} {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} g_1[v;B]=2,\\ g_2[v;B]=-p_1-p_2.\\ \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
  2. (b)

    Otherwise

    $$\begin{aligned} g_i[v;B]=\Lambda _i^{{\varvec{p}}}[v;B]\quad \text { for each }i\in N. \end{aligned}$$

    DP, BC, TP and WU are clearly satisfied by g. However, this power index fails to satisfy TR for game \(v=u^{\{1\}}\vee u^{\{2\}}\) and the trivial coalition structure \(B=B^n\).

\(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Carreras, F., Puente, M.A. On the axiomatic characterization of the coalitional multinomial probabilistic values. TOP 30, 119–151 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11750-021-00603-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11750-021-00603-3

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

Navigation